The philosophy of higher education

Its time has come

The ecological university, entangled with eight ecosystems (Barnett, 2022, p. 240)

The emergence of a field

It is time, it is the time, for the philosophy of higher education to announce its presence. As far back as the 1970s, there were one or two despatch riders heralding the phrase ‘the philosophy of higher education’ (Brubacher, 1978; Niblett, 1979, quoted in Barnett, 1990), but it was not until the 1990s that the field began to form. My own book, The Idea of Higher Education (1990), set out deliberately to give impetus to this nascent formation, to instigate the philosophy of higher education as a field of study in its own right, adjacent to (certainly) but distinct from the philosophy of education, with its own location and problematics. And through the 1990s and into the twenty-first century, the field has not just grown in size but has filled out, such that its scholarship has already formed sub-fields.

As if struck by lightning, the field has already split into two trunks, one concerned with the idea and the role of the university in society and the world, and the other concerned with higher education and what it is to be a student in a challenging world. To the first trunk attach branches such as the ideas of epistemic (in)justice, of the university in a digital age, of coloniality (and decolonisation), of institutional autonomy in an age, say, of ‘Empire,’ and the nature of knowledge (with urgings, for example, of ‘knowledge socialism’ [Peters and Besley, 2009] or of epistemic reparations). To the second trunk attach branches of the idea of critical thinking, of learning, of student becoming and of ‘critical-creative pedagogies’ (Schwittay, 2021). Crossover branches can also be spotted such as the ideas of academic identity, academic freedom and transdisciplinarity, and the place of religious traditions in realising higher education in the twenty-first century.

The sudden birth – with so little gestation – of this scholarly research is approaching a worldwide endeavour. The field, quite rightly, has spilt out into social theory and exhibits a proper fuzziness. Research students are working in the field, a learned society – the Philosophy and Theory of Higher Education Society (PaTHES) – was established in 2016 (and already has over one hundred paid-up members worldwide), there are at least two journals devoted to the field (with EPATmuch delving additionally in the territory), and there is a growing array of book series promoting the field (Springer, Routledge, Palgrave).

Like so many intellectual phenomena of this kind, it has – in a sense – just happened. It has no manifesto, no sense of direction, and no unifying theoretical or philosophical framing. It exhibits – to flag a number of themes from Deleuze and Guattari (2004) – so many ‘lines of flight,’ a ‘multiplicity’ of tropes and stances, moving in a ‘rhizomatic’ non-formation. Its movements are an amorphous ‘territorialisation,’ a territory without boundaries or guidelines.

Shall we just watch this effervescence at work and perhaps admire its growing energies and outpourings? Or might there be a case for taking stock of it all, and commenting on it, even critically so? There are surely several reasons for trying to do just this, of standing back and surveying the field and offering a view about it.

Firstly, research students work on discrete topics and deserve an overview of the field so that they can place their own efforts in that wider context and see where there can be contiguities. Secondly, universities have been establishing units both of academic development and learning development. Frequently, these units are linked to efforts by universities – perhaps elicited by state bodies – to assist their staff in becoming effective as teachers. Programmes and workshops are conducted that increasingly touch on philosophical and theoretical matters, and yet their participants – typically, new lecturers – understandably stumble in trying to fathom those matters. Thirdly, universities are sensing that the world is changing fundamentally – a world with increasing expectations of higher education – and so universities are re-setting their missions. In turn, university leaders are not infrequently wondering as to whether there are alternative frames of thinking hidden in the academic literature that might help them.

It is time, therefore, for the philosophy of higher education as an intellectual field to hide its light no longer. Its wares need to be assembled and sorted, and be accessible, such that those on the outside can wander around it in some comfort, looking with interest at what the shelves have to offer.

However, it is insufficient for the philosophy of higher education simply to expose its wares, hopefully to attract attention and even some fascination. If the philosophy of higher education is to fulfil its potential, it should become deeply reflexive. The field has to have a sense of its own becoming, of its situation and its possibilities and even – whisper it softly – its responsibilities. These responsibilities include a self-understanding that the field is a practical field and has, therefore, a responsibility to reach out to practitioners – leaders, managers, policy-makers – in the character of its writing; and even to form new publics across the world for its texts.

All this – and even somewhat more – I have attempted in my recent book The Philosophy of Higher Education: A Critical Introduction (Barnett, 2022). In it, I not only give an account of the field of the philosophy of higher education but, en route, I exemplify a particular philosophy of higher education. Perhaps I might try to say a little about this venture of mine.

Crisis – what crisis?

For many years – at least as far back as the second World War – scholars writing about higher education have used the term ‘crisis’ (Moberly, 1949). Originally, they were referring to the world being in crisis, to which it was felt that the university should respond (having signally failed to respond in the 1930s). From around the 1980s onwards, it was felt that it was higher education itself that was in crisis, whether that crisis was financial, epistemic (with the diminution of the humanities), purpose (as universities were being called upon to serve a bewildering array of functions), value (it having come to be subject to money values) or – and most recently – of justice (whether of epistemic justice, coloniality, or feminism). We were even told that the university was ‘in ruins’ (Readings, 1997).

There is a problem with all of these accusations of crisis, especially those aimed at crises within the university, namely that by and large, higher education has continued to grow relentlessly, right across the world and to have increasing influence and significance. On the surface, at least, higher education seems to be larger, more productive, more prized and more wanted than ever before. The ruins seem reluctant to fall.

However, there IS a deeper crisis, and we may put it very simply: it is a dual crisis of instrumentalism and extractivism, and this is a crisis both of the wider world and of the university itself. Some would trace this crisis back to origins in the Enlightenment; others, yet much further, back to the Greeks. I prefer the Enlightenment story of the origins of instrumentalism for the Enlightenment was characterised by the parallel tracks both of science and of philosophy separating humanity from the world, starting a lineage that runs right through to the present day, producing a series of dualities, of humanity-Nature, mind-body, person-community, and (ultimately) science-humanities.

To be sure, the element of instrumentalism that has come to pervade systematic inquiry characterised by the university is relatively recent, perhaps picking up steam after World War Two, but its origins lay in the dominant epistemology associated with the idea of science that originated in the Enlightenment. The laboratory, that material signifier of science as an academic practice, embodies not only an instrumentalism but significantly also control, as it seeks to sequestrate a particular feature of the natural world and perform its operations on it.

The university has been absolutely central in this narrative and in two ways. It has not only incorporated science – which in its early forms was a matter of home-based amateurs – but has become a site for its development and vast expansion, such that we now speak of ‘STEM’ without explanation – although now morphing into ‘STEMM’ (to include medicine [Cohen, 2021]) – and ‘global science.’ Universities worldwide are forming collective endeavours, with an exponential rise in the number of papers produced jointly across nations (especially between China and the USA &/or the UK). Second, the university has spawned not just ‘academic capitalism’ (Slaughter & Rhoades, 2009) – that is, put its knowledges directly into knowledge markets – but has become integral to the formation of cognitive capitalism (Boutang, 2011), and now morphing still further into a bio-informational and algorithmic capitalism (Peters, 2013).

Nine elements

Against this background, it cannot be sufficient for the philosophy of higher education to attend piecemeal to matters, even if they include large matters such as those, say, of sustainability, feminism, coloniality, digitalisation and (in)justice. Nor is it sufficient to focus just on the university as an institution and its place in the world or, alternatively, on the student experience and the student as, say, a customer in a neo-liberal age. And nor is it proper to demonise science – for science is now more needed than ever before (and it has shown its capabilities in the recent pandemic).

I suggest that the philosophy of higher education should be ambitious and possess no less than nine elements. It should be:

  • Conceptual: It has to evince a care for concepts, not just in ferreting out their past and historic meanings but also to glimpse their possibilities; to discern gaps between the potential of key concepts and their societal instantiation (Adorno, 2007); and to create new concepts (Deleuze & Guattari, 1996), here of the university and higher education.
  • Societal: One could easily say that the philosophy of higher education has to be a species of ‘social philosophy.’ However, that is far too vague a notion and underplays the fact that universities are now deeply embedded in society, a society that exerts pulls and pushes towards higher education. The philosophy of higher education accordingly has to be acutely societal, critiquing the presences of higher education in the world, so as to form a legitimate basis for feasible new concepts.
  • Critical: By critical, I have in mind simply that a philosophy of higher education should keep a certain distance from all that it surveys, not only the character of the world but also any intellectual currents in which it may be tempted to swim, even while it swims in them (around coloniality, academic freedom, digitalisation, ecologism and so forth). But much more so, its criticality will be evident in its keeping its eye open for absences, again not only in higher education itself but in the themes through which higher education and universities are being depicted. In Bhaskar’s (2008) language, it should ‘absent absences.’
  • Spiritual: This is an absence in itself. Where, for example, other than in the work of Karl Jaspers (1959) and, more recently, Bernard Stiegler (2014), do we see serious reference to the matter of ‘spirit’ in this context, as in the spirit of the university or in the kind of spirit that might be engendered in students? The idea that there might be a spiritual element in higher education – even in this energised sense – is largely repudiated altogether.
  • Ecological: Having just above suggested that the ecological strain is one to be wary of, nevertheless, I want to suggest that it is imperative that it be explicitly embraced by the philosophy of higher education. To say this is not simply to imply that our thought about universities and higher education should be encouraging an awareness of climate change, important as that is. It is rather to posit the matter of being, of human being in relation to the total inter-connectedness of the world. Yes, we see an instrumentalism toward Nature lying within the dominant epistemology that has been endorsed by universities over the past two hundred years, and especially so over the last three-quarters of a century or so, but we can also see many brave efforts to fashion new pedagogies and new institutional forms. In prospect, here, is a task for the philosophy for higher education to be a philosophy of eco-realism.
  • Imaginative: The philosophy of higher education cannot simply be describing or even critiquing matters. It has a responsibility to discern gaps between existing concepts and their instantiation in the world and so go on to forge new concepts and shapes that might better equip higher education to address a wide array of responsibilities in and on Earth, and to glimpse – however hazily – new kinds of institution and practices that might constitute universities.
  • Practical: If it be judged that higher education is deficient in some way, perhaps because it falls short of the concept (of higher education), or it exhibits unjustified absences that might be absented (Bhaskar [2008]), or (à la Derrida [2001]) that it is being suffocated by undue conditions placed upon it, or that (à la Hardt and Negri [2001, p. xii]) it has been swept up into an ‘empire’ of ‘decentred and derritorialising apparatus of rule,’ or any other such insights, then the philosophy of higher education has a responsibility to eke out, in broad terms, principles that can assist in re-orienting the ship. The philosophy of higher education cannot form a manifesto for all disciplines, for all universities and for higher education across all nations, but it can and should discern broad principles for universities and their major activities.
  • Value-sensitive: To be alert to the way the world is, is to have a concern for it, and so it is to have an interest in what might be helpful to the world. The educational and institutional oughts derive from concerns about the ‘is’ of the world. No ‘is’ can straightforwardly be read off the world. But impairments in the various ecosystems of the world can be identified, and, with those identifications, so can responsibilities begin to suggest themselves for any serious philosophy of higher education; and discernment of responsibilities would be prompted by values being brought to bear. To be sure, these would also, for a university and higher education, be always open to critique and would have to be justified.
  • Feasibly utopian: Given the weight of the steering mechanisms in the world that are energised by partial interests, any attempt to form serious institutional and education programmes would be utopian. They would hold in view futures not yet before us nor likely to be fully realised. To gain legitimacy, these utopias should be feasible They should be realisable in the best of possible worlds; and their possibilities may be evident, in that – if only fleetingly and spasmodically – instances may be glimpsed across the world of higher education.

An eco-realism of and for higher education

This is a future-oriented and hopeful realism. It springs from readings of the world that reach into the deep structures of the world and, on that basis, that furnish glimpses of possible worlds. They gain legitimacy, too, by providing practical principles that can be cashed out, at the level both of the university as an institution and its many activities, including its teaching programmes, their pedagogies and students’ experiences.

It is also, as stated, an eco-realism, beginning from a sense of the inter-connectedness of the world – its ‘relationality’ – and is intent on using the resources of the university and its study programmes collectively to address the way the world is. The natural environment (as an ecosystem or set of ecosystems) is not privileged in this venture, not least because it is partly through the impairments in other ecosystems – of knowledge, the economy, culture, social institutions, learning and so on – that the natural environment is in the plight that has befallen it.

This philosophy of higher education is no blueprint philosophy. Each university, each set of staff and students have collectively to work through and imaginatively discern possibilities for their own institution, their own study programme, their own research centre or their own efforts to engage with the wider world.

This is a philosophy of higher education for the totality of all that is in the world, in and on this Earth and, indeed, from the Earth. It discerns its possibilities – both in idea and in practice in our institutions of higher education – from its value-oriented readings of the way that the world is. It is a realist philosophy of higher education, containing a strong ontological dimension, and wanting to assist universities and higher education in helping to make better this small Earth – not least in assisting the rectification of the maladies of this Earth that universities in part have brought about. It is an eco-realism of and for higher education.

This is a redemptive philosophy of higher education, but it is also a questful philosophy. Whether there is time for such a philosophy of higher education to have any serious influence remains to be seen.

References

Adorno, T. (2014). Negative dialectics. Bloomsbury.

Barnett, R. (1990). The idea of higher education. McGraw-Hill Education.

Barnett, R. (2022). The philosophy of higher education: A critical introduction. Routledge.

Bhasker, R. (2008). Dialectic: The pulse of freedom. Routledge.

Boutang, Y-M. (2011). Cognitive capitalism. Polity.

Brubacher, J. S. (1978). On the philosophy of higher education. Jossey-Bass.

Cohen, E. (2021). The university and its boundaries: Thriving or surviving in the 21st century. Routledge.

Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2004). A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and schizophrenia. Continuum.

Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1996). What is philosophy? Verso.

Derrida, J. (2001). The future of the profession or the university without condition (thanks to the ‘humanities,’ what could take place tomorrow). In T. Cohen (Ed.), Jacques Derrida and the humanities (pp. 24–57). Cambridge University Press.

Hardt, M., & Negri, A. (2001). Empire. Harvard.

Jaspers, K. (1959). The idea of the university. Beacon Press.

Moberly, W. (1949). The crisis in the university. SCM.

Peters, M. A. (2013). Education, science and knowledge capitalism: Creativity and the promise of openness. Peter Lang.

Peters, M. A., with Besley, A. C. (2009). Building knowledge cultures: Education and development in the age of knowledge capitalism. Rowman & Littlefield.

Readings, B. (1997). The university in ruins. Harvard.

Schwittay, A. (2021). Creative universities: Reimagining education for global challenges and alternative futures. Bristol University Press.

Slaughter, S., & Rhoades, G. (2009). Academic capitalism and the new economy: Markets, state and higher education.Johns Hopkins University.

Stiegler, B. (2014). The re-enchantment of the world: The value of spirit against industrial populism. Bloomsbury.

Share this article on Social Media

Full Citation Information:
Barnett, R. (2022). The philosophy of higher education: Its time has come. PESA Agora. https://pesaagora.com/columns/the-philosophy-of-higher-education/

Ronald Barnett

Ronald Barnett is Emeritus Professor of Higher Education, University College London. He is the inaugural President of the Philosophy and Theory in Higher Education Society. His recent books include The Philosophy of Higher Education: A Critical Introduction (Routledge, 2022)